EUR 12,90
  • Alle Preisangaben inkl. MwSt.
Nur noch 11 auf Lager (mehr ist unterwegs).
Verkauf und Versand durch Amazon.
Geschenkverpackung verfügbar.
Menge:1
Ihren Artikel jetzt
eintauschen und
EUR 3,15 Gutschein erhalten.
Möchten Sie verkaufen?
Zur Rückseite klappen Zur Vorderseite klappen
Anhören Wird wiedergegeben... Angehalten   Sie hören eine Probe der Audible-Audioausgabe.
Weitere Informationen
Alle 2 Bilder anzeigen

Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy: Third Edition (Englisch) Taschenbuch – 4. November 2008


Alle 2 Formate und Ausgaben anzeigen Andere Formate und Ausgaben ausblenden
Amazon-Preis Neu ab Gebraucht ab
Gebundene Ausgabe
"Bitte wiederholen"
EUR 71,37
Taschenbuch
"Bitte wiederholen"
EUR 12,90
EUR 8,04 EUR 18,09
45 neu ab EUR 8,04 6 gebraucht ab EUR 18,09

Hinweise und Aktionen

  • Studienbücher: Ob neu oder gebraucht, alle wichtigen Bücher für Ihr Studium finden Sie im großen Studium Special. Natürlich portofrei.


Wird oft zusammen gekauft

Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy: Third Edition + The Road to Serfdom: Text and Documents - the Definitive Edition + Capitalism and Freedom: Fortieth Anniversary Edition
Preis für alle drei: EUR 43,23

Die ausgewählten Artikel zusammen kaufen
Jeder kann Kindle Bücher lesen — selbst ohne ein Kindle-Gerät — mit der KOSTENFREIEN Kindle App für Smartphones, Tablets und Computer.


Produktinformation

  • Taschenbuch: 464 Seiten
  • Verlag: Harper Perennial Modern Classics; Auflage: unknown (4. November 2008)
  • Sprache: Englisch
  • ISBN-10: 0061561614
  • ISBN-13: 978-0061561610
  • Größe und/oder Gewicht: 13,5 x 2,7 x 20,3 cm
  • Durchschnittliche Kundenbewertung: 4.0 von 5 Sternen  Alle Rezensionen anzeigen (1 Kundenrezension)
  • Amazon Bestseller-Rang: Nr. 41.701 in Fremdsprachige Bücher (Siehe Top 100 in Fremdsprachige Bücher)

Mehr über den Autor

Entdecken Sie Bücher, lesen Sie über Autoren und mehr

Produktbeschreibungen

Pressestimmen

“The 20th century’s foremost economist.” (Steve Forbes, Forbes)

“The most influential economist of the 20th century.” (Peter Drucker, Fortune)

“The great economist Joseph Schumpeter highlighted the role of innovation in powering the rise of new industries, the creative destruction of existing ones, and the growth in prosperity of economies.” (Richard Florida, Atlantic)

“Schumpeter gave us stunning insights into how the world really works. We are now living, it is said, in the Age of Schumpeter. . . . Schumpeter was a powerful prophet, and he now offers dazzling insights into everything from the rise of Wal-Mart to prosperity’s discontents.” (Robert J. Samuelson, Newsweek)

“The greatest defense of capitalist, European civilization ever penned. . . . Schumpeter did more than anyone to persuade American leaders to preserve the capitalist system” (American Conservative)

“Schumpeter may well be the most important economist of the 21st century.” (J. Bradford DeLong, Chronicle of Higher Education)

“Schumpeter was the most farsighted of twentieth-century economists. His focus on capitalism and creative destruction made him the prophet of globalization.” (The Nation)

Über den Autor und weitere Mitwirkende

Joseph A. Schumpeter (1883-1950) served as Austria's first finance minister, made and lost a fortune as an investment banker, and taught economics for many years at Harvard. Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy is his best-known work.


Welche anderen Artikel kaufen Kunden, nachdem sie diesen Artikel angesehen haben?


In diesem Buch (Mehr dazu)
Ausgewählte Seiten ansehen
Buchdeckel | Copyright | Inhaltsverzeichnis | Auszug | Stichwortverzeichnis | Rückseite
Hier reinlesen und suchen:

Kundenrezensionen

4.0 von 5 Sternen
5 Sterne
0
4 Sterne
1
3 Sterne
0
2 Sterne
0
1 Sterne
0
Siehe die Kundenrezension
Sagen Sie Ihre Meinung zu diesem Artikel

Die hilfreichsten Kundenrezensionen

0 von 1 Kunden fanden die folgende Rezension hilfreich Von Michael am 14. April 2012
Format: Taschenbuch Verifizierter Kauf
This book is crucial for anyone of a free-market bent. Schumpeter's creative destruction is key to understanding the workings of the market.
Kommentar War diese Rezension für Sie hilfreich? Ja Nein Feedback senden...
Vielen Dank für Ihr Feedback. Wenn diese Rezension unangemessen ist, informieren Sie uns bitte darüber.
Wir konnten Ihre Stimmabgabe leider nicht speichern. Bitte erneut versuchen

Die hilfreichsten Kundenrezensionen auf Amazon.com (beta)

Amazon.com: 17 Rezensionen
22 von 26 Kunden fanden die folgende Rezension hilfreich
The big picture 13. November 2010
Von Jake Le Master - Veröffentlicht auf Amazon.com
Format: Taschenbuch
This is a theme which gives Schumpeter the opportunity to appear at his best. He approaches questions of institutions and economic tendencies from the standpoint of a lively and wide interest in human nature.

The book starts with a critical examination of Marxian doctrine -- Marx the Prophet succeeded in "weaving together those extra-rational cravings which receding religion had left running about like masterless dogs, and the rationalistic and materialistic tendencies of the time" (p. 6). Marx the Sociologist "linked the fate of the class phenomenon with the fate of capitalism " (p. 19). Marx the Economist was a follower of Ricardo (p. 22), but not merely a follower. His one truly great achievement was "to see and to teach systematically how economic theory may be turned into historical analysis, and how the historical narrative may be turned into histoire raisonnie", instead of assigning the facts of economic history "to a separate compartment" (p. 44).

There follows Part II, "Can Capitalism Survive?" Schumpeter has his own individual view of the working of capitalism. The Marxian theory of exploitation, depending on the effect of a perpetual reserve of labor in keeping wages down to the subsistence level, is disproved by experience (pp. 34-7). He himself belongs to the school of thought which treats profit as an excrescence of the economic system, so that in the stationary state neither profit nor interest would exist.

Profit in his view is derived from "innovations", and he uses the term "entrepreneur" for one who initiates an innovation. "The fundamental impulse that sets and keeps the capitalist engine in motion comes from the new consumers' goods, the new methods of production or transportation, the new markets, the new forms of industrial organisation, that capitalist enterprise creates" (p. 83). "In dealing with capitalism, we are dealing with an evolutionary proces "; capitalism "is by nature a form or method of economic change, and not only never is but never can be stationary".

Even monopoly profits are of slight significance, though "there is or may be an element of genuine monopoly gain in those entrepreneurial profits which are the prizes offered by capitalist society to the successful innovator" (p. 102).

"Can capitalism survive?" Professor Schumpeter asks. "No, I do not think it can," he replies (p. 61).

It might be supposed that, if innovation is "the fundamental impulse that sets and keeps the capitalist engine in motion", the end would come through an exhaustion of possible innovations. In Chapter X he turns to consider the prospect of a "vanishing of investment opportunity ". In his opinion "there is no reason to expect slackening of the rate of output through exhaustion of technological possibilities" (p. 118), even when "capital-saving" devices pre-dominate (pp. 119-20). But in Chapter XII he poses the possibility that "the economic wants of humanity might be so completely satisfied that little motive would be left to push productive effort still further ahead" (p. 131). If improvements in methods of production were also assumed to have reached their limit, "a more or less stationary state would ensue...There would be nothing left for entrepreneurs to do...Profits and, along with profits, the rate of interest would converge towards zero. The bourgeois strata that live on profits and interest would tend to disappear."

"For the calculable future," Schumnpeter comments, "this vision is of no importance. But all the greater importance attaches to the fact that many of the effects...can also be expected from a development that is clearly observable already. Progress itself may be mechanised."

For, he explains (p. 132), "innovation itself is being reduced to routine. Technological progress is increasingly becoming the business of teams of trained specialists who turn out what is required and make it work in predictable ways...Thus economic progress tends to become depersonalised and automatised. Bureau and committee work tends to replace individual action" (p. 133). The part played by the capitalist entrepreneur ceases to be one of individual leadership, acting by virtue of personal force and personal responsibility for success, and this affects the entire bourgeois stratum which hitherto has been recruited and revitalized by absorbing the entrepreneurs and their families. The bourgeoisie "depends on the entrepreneur, and as a class lives and will die with him".

"If capitalist evolution -- 'progress' -- either ceases, or becomes completely automatic, the economic basis of the industrial bourgeoisie will be reduced eventually to wages such as are paid for current administrative work, excepting remnants of quasi-rents and monopoloid gains that may be expected to linger on for some time" (p. 119). There is, no doubt, a tendency for the individual freelance innovator to be superseded by the big concern. The big concern can supply finance and organization for new departures outside its original scope. And the opportunities may be discovered by individuals in its own employment.

But it is not clear that this portends a decay of capitalism. It may transform the character of the middle class, but Schumpeter maintains that the middle class hitherto evolved by capitalism has lacked the qualities essential for political leadership, and has depended on the remnants of feudalism to provide a governing class. May not the new middle class be better qualified not only to conduct economic activity but to animate a political community? In any case, if it is an approximation to a socialist middle class, presumably a completely socialist middle class will manage no better.

His view of the future is shaped by his theory of profit. And his idea that without individual innovating enterprise profit will vanish or become unimportant is surely a profound miscalculation. Indeed, his theory is one more instance of the propensity of economists to explain away profit. Marx's theory of exploitation belongs to the fallacies of a past age. But the present age has its fallacies too. The profit-making which communism would suppress is not dependent on innovations or on monopolies. It arises, with all its anomalies and abuses, from the mechanism of competition and is the remuneration of selling power. It would persist therefore in the stationary state, or under conditions of depersonalized and automatized progress. Profit-making would still be the object of attack. In proportion as the profit-makers become fewer in numbers, they become more open to attack by the multitude, whether by revolutionary action or by the peaceful operation of democracy.

Between socialism and democracy, as conceived by Schumpeter, there is no necessary connection, but there is no incompatibility (p. 284). He is skeptical of the classical doctrine of democracy, postulating a popular will (Chapter XXI). But his own definition of it, as a method "by which individuals acquire the power to decide [in the political field] by means of a competitive struggle for the people's vote", is surely not adequate. The competitive struggle, occurring when there is a cleavage of opinion, and parties offer alternative governments, is a frequent and lively development in democracies. But it often happens that there is no competition and no struggle; the preference of the electorate for a particular group of statesmen is recognized to be decisive, and oppositions are confined to occasional bodies of criticism.

Moreover, the struggle for power, if it is to be democratic, must be one of persuasion. Actual democracies are imperfect, and persuasion is adulterated with intimidation or corruption.

Schumpeter's attitude to democracy as well as to socialism and capitalism is that of a tolerant but ironic critic. Whoever is carried away by great issues, it will not be he. But that is a very salutary approach. His book is full of wisdom, even though of a detached and fatalistic kind.
11 von 12 Kunden fanden die folgende Rezension hilfreich
Something for everyone... 4. Februar 2011
Von Brian C. - Veröffentlicht auf Amazon.com
Format: Taschenbuch
Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy is divided up into five main sections. The first section on Marx and the last section on the history of the socialist parties in Europe can be safely skipped by most readers. The three central sections on capitalism, socialism, and democracy are definitely the heart of the book and of the three central sections the section on capitalism is by far the most interesting.

In the section on capitalism Schumpeter really tries to do two things. First, he attempts to provide a defense for capitalism based on its dynamic nature. Schumpeter is critical of the defenses of capitalism which base themselves on the notion that under perfect competition "the profit interest of the producer tends to maximize production" (pg77). In two footnotes Schumpeter explains the problems he has with this standard defense of capitalism.

In the first he writes, "The principle, as far as it can be proved at all, applies to a state of static equilibrium. Capitalist reality is first and last a process of change. In appraising performance of competitive enterprise, the question whether it would or would not tend to maximize production in a perfectly equilibrated stationary condition of the economic process is hence almost, though not quite, irrelevant" (pg77). The standard defense relies on the notion that under perfect competition (a state in which prices are parameters and not variables) production will take place up until the point that marginal cost just equals price. It is further argued that this is precisely "as much as it is in general `socially desirable' to produce" (pg78). But as Schumpeter points out in his footnote this only takes place when the economy is in a state of static equilibrium. Since a capitalist economic system is never in such a state the defense becomes (almost) irrelevant.

In the second footnote Schumpeter is responding to a closely related theorem, namely, the theorem that competitive industry tends to produce a maximum satisfaction of wants. Schumpeter writes, "this theorem, even if we waive the serious objections to speaking of non-observable psychic magnitudes, is readily seen to boil down to the triviality that, whatever the data and in particular the institutional arrangements of a society may be, human action, as far as it is rational, will always try to make the best of any given situation. In fact it boils down to a definition of rational action and can hence be paralleled by analogous theorems for, say, a socialist society" (pg77). Utlimately the defense of capitalism which rests on the notion that perfect competition leads to a maximum satisfaction of wants boils down to the proposition that given any set of parameters (consumption preferences, capital allocations, technical levels, etc.) human beings will tend to make the most that they can with what they have. This applies to any institutional form and is not specific to capitalism.

Schumpeter offers a different (and in my opinion a better) defense of capitalism by pointing to its dynamic character. Schumpeter argues that capitalism is a process which is constantly engaged in revolutionizing the means of production (creative destruction) as entrepeneurs seek `super profits'. This dramatically increases the total output of society and a huge share of this increased output winds up finding its way to the lower classes of society. As Schumpeter says, "There are no doubt some things available to the modern workman that Louis XIV would have been delighted to have yet was unable to have...On the whole, however, a budget on that level had little that really mattered to gain from capitalist achievement" (pg67). The Louis XIV's of the world are not primarily the ones who benefit from the dynamic of the capitalist system since the capitalist system is overwhelming geared towards mass production and so produces goods that can be consumed cheaply by the masses. This defense of capitalism does not rely on any theorems about maximizing utility under perfect competition and is a far more realistic defense of the advantages of a social system that is ruled by the profit motive.

The second goal of Schumpeter's section on capitalism is to describe the ways in which the processes unleashed by capitalism tend, inexorably, to undermine its own foundations. The most interesting example of this is the way in which property comes to be redefined through the joint stock company. There is a separation of ownership and management. The role of the entrepreneur also begins to erode as the process of creative destruction becomes mechanized and standardized. Instead of the adventurous entrepreneur taking a chance on a new idea we have corporations and their programs of research and development. One of the great virtues of Schumpeter's work is that he manages to avoid viewing things from a restrictively economic standpoint and is able to see the importance of sociological factors in determining the behavior of the economic sphere. So Schumpeter also spends some time discussing sociological changes brought about by capitalism which in turn have an effect on the economic process (family relations for example)

In the section on socialism Schumpeter attempts to work out a logical blueprint for a socialist society that would be capable of solving all the problems that a free-market is able to solve (the allocation of capital, provision for public goods, incentives and motivations for workers and managers, etc.). Schumpeter attempts to argue that there is at least no logical reason why socialism could not work. I am not sure he is entirely successful but this section is at least thought provoking and indicative of the problems that socialists necessarily face in constructing an alternative social arrangement for production and distribution.

In the final section on democracy Schumpeter attempts to reconceive democracy as a competition for political leadership. Democracy is not the rule of the people for Schumpeter, rather, democracy is "the rule of the politician" (pg285). Public policy, on this view, becomes merely a by-product of political competition. This is probably a more realistic picture of how democracy really works then the standard view but it relies on the notion that human beings have far less awareness and knowledge in regard to affairs that do not concern them directly, or that they do not deal with on an everyday basis, and, therefore, do not have strong opinions one way or another. They can be swayed by politicians. In other words, this is not necessarily an analysis of the `eternal' nature of democracy. If human beings were to achieve a better grasp of social issues this vision of democracy might not apply.

In summary, this book is definitely worth reading. Although the first and last sections can be skipped and if you are really in a hurry you can simply read the section on capitalism and you definitely will have read the most interesting and the most influential section of this work.
9 von 11 Kunden fanden die folgende Rezension hilfreich
The Glorious System 23. Juli 2009
Von Stergios D. Marangos - Veröffentlicht auf Amazon.com
Format: Taschenbuch Verifizierter Kauf
* This is a long review, if you would not like to read it all you may skip to the last paragraph *

** Additionally, the large strength of this book is its defense and description of modern capitalist development and progress. Part II of the book, that is. The rest is actually not very good. So, buy this book because 1. Capitalism's best description/defense in both a socioeconomic and political context 2. Schumpeter is one of the most important economists to know of if you want to take the subject matter seriously. **

Schumpeter opens part II of Capitalism, Socialism, and Democracy, after a lengthy bit pertaining to Karl Marx `the Prophet, the Sociologist, the Economist, the Teacher' wherein he graces us with his knowledge of Marx's major strengths and flaws (sometimes correct and incorrect himself, and sometimes degenerating into complete fiction), with an ominous sentence - `Can Capitalism survive? No, I do not think it can' (p. 61). Later, in part III of the book, he opens with another - `Can Socialism work? Of course it can.' (p. 167). To unravel these two seemingly complementary statements, we must first investigate the capitalist mode of production as according to Schumpeter, how it came to fruition, and investigate what processes, either endogenous or exogenous, he believes will be the cause of its purported demise and replacement by a `socialist' mode of production.

Schumpeter believed that the most essential feature of the capitalist mode of production was to be found in the constant revolutionizing of the productive forces; a `perennial gale of creative destruction', as he said, that comes about through the introduction of new technologies and, with them, the obsolescence of the old. Without this feature, he claimed that Capitalism "would be like Hamlet without the Danish price" (p. 86). He was naturally highly critical of the neoclassical economic doctrine which purported to explain capitalist production through `perfect competition' paradigms. To Schumpeter, perfect competition was not only a myth but a dangerous one at that.
For Schumpeter then, the idea that competition in capitalist production existed only as a quantitative relationship between firms, finding its vehicle in price, was fantasy. Atomistic competition, even if it ever had existed (which is in itself not so clear) would simply be unable to reach the level of accumulation needed to both survive the `perennial gale' and reproduce itself. An economy characterized by atomistic competition would be in a constant state of flux, with firms (or `individual producers') too rapidly exiting and entering the market and profit rates being driven down to the point that the negation of the crucial role of firms - the ability to accumulate to the point necessary for reinvestment - would be the ultimate cost of such `free' competition. This economy would in the short run be unstable and in the long run stagnant due to the lack of new methods and technologies being introduced for continual reinvestment. Instead, Schumpeter saw competition as a qualitative relationship - one which firms large enough to maintain a profit rate that allowed for reinvestment in strategic and technical improvements and competition in the sphere of research and development, in addition to being able to build up strong reserves for lifesaving mechanisms, would ultimately triumph.
Schumpeter did not believe that capitalist production could be adequately defended on the grounds of short-run considerations. Within the economic system, as a byproduct of quality competition and strategic planning, was taking place a process which revealed itself only through intervals of time in quality improvements and the application of technological innovation. Therefore, holding time as a constant was in effect blinding one of this crucial aspect. This process drove innovations that contributed to higher productivity and lower costs, making the formerly inaccessible accessible to the masses. In this respect, efficiency for Schumpeter was a long run concept that was more related to efficiency of the system as a whole than to productive efficiency at a given point in time. This process took place, as Marx would have said, `behind our backs'. And, accordingly, focusing on short run resource utilization, or full employment as was becoming quite the trend in Keynesian economics, was for Schumpeter even more than what focusing on supply and demand was for Marx - not only misguided but ruinous to long term systemic efficiency. The kind of activity responsible for reoccurring technological revolutions and subsequent relative prosperity was not compatible with equilibrium. Indeed, it had a tendency toward, if not only functional with, a state of disequilibrium.

Mature capitalist production, as depicted above, was for Schumpeter a product of a historically specific process. The main actor in this process was a specific group of people not belonging to any specific class in particular; entrepreneurs. The dynamic nature of the capitalist mode of production was simply a byproduct of the entrepreneur's thirst for individual achievement, which in turn created whole new industries through sheer force of will and determination, simultaneously sweeping away the old order of things (p. 132). These `movers' built the foundations of the mature capitalist system through individual achievement in innovation - the only way possible to rise to a bourgeois standing in a bourgeois world.
This depiction of the entrepreneur has no regard for one's social class, standing, or means in determining who would rise to the challenge of fulfilling the entrepreneurial function. The siren call of wealth and the fostering of a culture of meritocracy thereby pulled people from all walks of life to fill the role of the entrepreneur. The rationalization of all elements of life, fostered by capitalist production, further spurred individuals of exceptional intelligence and drive from all strata to fill this role through the rejection of metaphysical explanations of events and extra worldly existence; furthermore, an atmosphere that imbued them with a belief in individual merit and achievement and an acceptance of the material world as final put individuals in the position to discard notions of heavenly intervention and design, replacing them with a conscience belief in their own abilities to do the same. In this regard, Schumpeter explained the huge leaps in technology and the masses of commodities being made available during and after the industrial revolution both by the growing relative freedom with which the entrepreneur was able to perform his or her social function and an atmosphere conducive to individual achievement.

At its height, the Schumpeterian entrepreneur represented an extension of the notion that clusters of talented people have been the driving force behind history, thereby itself occupying a historic position in social organization quite similar to that held by the stratum formerly populated with owners and masters. The owner of men, whipping his lazy property towards production and progress; the feudal lord, so graciously giving the means to the lower classes of society to survive, not to mention provide for the landed class; and finally the entrepreneur rising to the bourgeois ranks, putting the toiling masses to productive work through the implementation of his or her `vision of things'. The belief in the inability of the masses of people to produce (to Schumpeter's liking) or to maintain political and social order (in Schumpeter's conception) runs straight through this in perfect sequence, with the difference being, of course, that the bourgeois way of imposing oneself in the middle of the production process is much less `physical' - As Marx would say, its true nature is concealed.
This relation, however, is similar only to the extent that the entrepreneur is both an essential part of a specific mode of production - thereby in his or her present obtaining the status tied to this role - and bound to be replaced when that mode becomes outdated - thereby in the future being seen as the remnant of an outdated and forgotten past. The political stratum of elites, as mentioned earlier, was of an altogether different breed than the bourgeoisie - the bourgeoisie budded from merchant and middle classes of society whereas the political elite, or aristocracy, carried on from landed owners and nobility for centuries past. Unlike the former `movers' of society, who played an important ruling role in addition to others, Schumpeter's soon-to-be bourgeoisie had little interest in the heroic or romantic and little interest or skill in the leading and ruling of men 9. Their interest and ambition, according to Schumpeter, went as far as their pocketbooks could take them confined, of course, to bourgeois commercial and productive endeavors - what their `normal work and mentality fit into' (p. 128).

It is of importance to note here what is lacking in Schumpeter's glorious conception of capitalist production. We have, I think, established that the system as a whole is akin to the machine and the budding bourgeois entrepreneur the engine, but we have not yet provided the fuel. Nor did Schumpeter feel inclined to dirty himself with this task. We must therefore turn to someone who was more at home in the industrial factories and coal mines of the world than the thin upper layer of social `movers' - As Marx would have reminded us, the fuel is of course the laborer. The toiling masses, however, could not be a part of this picture, less they would detract from its immutable splendor. Schumpeter offers an original solution to this problem. He simply erased the toiling masses, or, in effect, depicted their part in the `perennial gale' as that of a mere nuisance; An insect being blown about only to crash on a windshield and constrict ones view of the beautiful road in front of him; An undisciplined, inferior being, unable to climb the ladder of success. In the working masses was to be found the problem - a fetter on the class that always looked to the long run - not the solution 10. Workers, those who produced the objects dreamt up by the entrepreneur - the mass of people everywhere - were indebted to the entrepreneur for the vision of the thing, for that is what would, if only the process could continue, "lift poverty from the shoulders of mankind" (p. 129). We will return to this creature soon enough, for as much as Schumpeter tries to avoid it, it does rise from its irrelevance and come to play an important - though limited - role in the `crumbling walls of the bourgeois fortress. Even Schumpeter must recognize that the long run is too far away for the unfortunate that must live in the short run.

The bourgeoisie as a class and the entrepreneurial function are inexorably bound. It is the best and brightest of all lower strata of society that `free' themselves through this function, and from there it is but a step - a matter of success for the inherently successful - to bourgeois life. A successful entrepreneur, like a caterpillar, comes out of the cocoon as a different creature. This process is the lifeblood of the bourgeoisie both in the sense that the entrepreneur embodies the strength of the individualist creed - its strength therefore being the foundation of laissez faire - and because the bourgeoisie replenish their ranks - constantly falling through concentration of capitals - through it. The bourgeoisie as a class are therefore able to see what their future holds by looking at the state of entrepreneurship - its social standing, its political clout, its growth or decline.
Though the entrepreneur was not per se part of the bourgeois as a class, he or she had every intention and aspiration of becoming a part, and indeed their main purpose was to become bourgeois. This is a major point of contention in the Schumpeterian schema of things because once this goal has been achieved, once the butterfly emerges, the whole of economic organization begins to shift with it. Through his or her success, the entrepreneur contributes to the changing of the technological superstructure that provided for his or her functionality within the framework of a historically specific mode of production. As Schumpeter was pained to point out, both objective and subjective developments caused by this group's very success would spell the end of `individual achievement' as the driving force of social reproduction. Wrapped in Marxian historical necessity, the entrepreneurial function served its specific function in time by filling the open wound left from the removal of the fetters of former modes of production and, at its highest point, began revealing the fetters inherent in itself. Similar with former social roles and functions, the entrepreneurial function slowly begins to lose the weight that it once carried in economic and social affairs, while both objective and subjective factors begin to impede on its relevance. Through innovative success the entrepreneur essentially creates the conditions for his or her own irrelevance - the mechanization of innovation replacing individual drive and risk with a corporate structure that no longer lives and dies by individual achievement but by bureaucratic efficiency and managerial oversight and the position of the individual whose social role was to better him or herself through improvement of man's material existence becomes the position of the board of directors and managers who compete with other board of directors and managers. Once this process takes hold, the owning of one's own business or property - the success of which is tied to the individual - withers away as the institution morphs into a form of social ownership accountable to and run by myriad different actors.

The entrepreneurial function, as any historically specific process, then had both a time and place. For the innumerable personal strengths and virtues of a person are as much a product of the institutions and social existence he or she was nurtured in as anything else. When the planets and stars aligned - when the objective and subjective technological and social conditions were in place - the individualist spirit propelled by the entrepreneurial function and materializing
in the bourgeoisie as a class was unleashed to its historically necessary role. Bourgeois values attacked the old order of things - the irrationality, the heroics and romance, the Belief as opposed to the Fact. All were subject to the critical eye of rationalization. Their values simultaneously `freed' both the mind of the intellectual and the body of the slave. However, just as the breaking of so many fetters and the changing of so many traditions and beliefs was necessary before the bourgeoisie would be able to flourish, so were they the only forces maintaining the framework within which the bourgeois way of life was possible. The tragedy is that by lifting these barriers and tearing down these false Gods and natural Rights of the past they were actually destroying the framework within which their own interests were best served and, worse yet, spurring on a process the end result of which would be their own functional obsolescence. Their rationality and creed stretched as far as the individual, and in that sense they were both unable to defend their greater class interest and destroying the only class that could. The concept of something greater than one was completely alien to their scripture.
In the end, then, the entrepreneur was replaced by the bureaucrat and manager, who by virtue of the formers technological success was now able to automize his or her social function; the institutional framework within which the bourgeoisie developed was, from relentless bourgeois attack, forced to transformed from one in which the aristocracy both fed on bourgeois wealth to maintain itself and in turn championed bourgeois principles and legal requirements to one in which the `new' aristocracy - the aristocracy and elite morphed into the politicians, the bureaucrats, the military officers - were at best apathetic and at worst hostile to the individualistic creed; and, perhaps the greatest surprise to the bourgeoisie mind but not for hindsight, the rationalizing and critical mindset fostered by bourgeois values turned upon itself. No longer suspended through threats of physical harm or death; no longer subject to witchcraft `trials' or heretic damnation, it turned its blade towards the father that unwittingly made its existence possible. The intellectual turned a critical eye to the bourgeois way of life and bourgeois institutions, and in doing so gave a new lease on life to that pitiful creature we alluded to earlier. The working masses of the world, unable just the same as their social forefathers to think and act for themselves, and without the fetters of the ancien régime to legitimize their obedience by metaphysical bondage, found their new social `leaders' in the intellectual.

We can identify certain key factors in Schumpeter's conception of the birth and death of capitalist production and the extent to which it is really socialism which he is predicting. Economically, he clearly believed that the functionality of advanced economies had long passed what bourgeois economic theory - `free' market theory - purported it to be, and readily defended concentration and `restrictive' practices as the new order of progress. He even went so far as to call private property a fetter on development, or in his words there were "obstacles that the institution of private property puts in the path of progress (p. 89). Socially, he viewed the situation as extremely precarious. The masses, spurred by intellectuals, were developing a deep seated hatred for the `private' control of production and bourgeois lifestyles in particular. The social role of the entrepreneur was being eroded by his or her own successes, and with its obsolescence bourgeois values were being picked apart. Politically, he saw it as hopeless that the bourgeoisie would be able to fill the role of the nobility or clergy that they themselves had forced out of custom, both because they did not know how to fill this role and because it was outside of their realm of interest.
That the capitalist order was in his eyes essentially the framework of a process not only of economic but social change is not disputed. However, his conception of `social change' seems to apply only to a higher stratum of society. While the upper echelons of society change, there seems to be little to no movement in the position of the mass of people on the bottom. The whole historical framework is essentially run by elite groups and subgroups of people - the entrepreneur, the bourgeois, the intellectual, the nobility. Nowhere does actual `rationalized' society come into play. Essentially, Schumpeterian socialism consists not of the majority of people having ownership of any means of production or even a say in the production process, but of formerly `individual' ownership becoming `joint' ownership by a board of directors or other socially superior elements. His socialism recognizes that there is society - a large leap for many of the bourgeois intellectual type - however only seems to care much for it to the extent that the social function of the unproductive class, in a material sense, maintains its intermediary role. In my opinion, though he claims it, he is completely misguided in the labeling of his future fantasy world as socialist. State-capitalist seems perhaps more appropriate. Schumpeter does, however, score largely when it comes to explaining the functionality of mature capitalist production at the highest level and identifying various trends and happenings within it. Most interesting in this regard, though said in passing, is his notion that the whole of the capitalist socioeconomic system was simply the final stage of the decomposition of feudalism - perhaps not even an independent social form at all (p 139).
2 von 2 Kunden fanden die folgende Rezension hilfreich
Excellent book 2. April 2013
Von Fox - Veröffentlicht auf Amazon.com
Format: Taschenbuch Verifizierter Kauf
Probably the best and most accurate book on this topic I've read to date. This book has a very good intro done by another author. Schumpeter gives evidence and makes comparisons for you, all you have to do is read, he did all the leg work.
1 von 1 Kunden fanden die folgende Rezension hilfreich
Joeseph Shumpeter's epic treatise on economics 26. Dezember 2012
Von john pepin - Veröffentlicht auf Amazon.com
Format: Gebundene Ausgabe Verifizierter Kauf
I bit hard to read this book was a watershed discussion on Marxian theory and capitalist economics. His ideas about the nature of entrepreneurial economic growth were groundbreaking. The term "creative destruction" is overused by people relating to his theories... in my opinion.
Waren diese Rezensionen hilfreich? Wir wollen von Ihnen hören.